Case study: Robot camel jockeys. Yes, really.

Introduction

Robot camel jockeys … yes, really.

Why this case study?

Robots are now widely used in place of child camel jockeys. The robots used in camel racing are so simple that they scarcely count as AI. Indeed, developments since their inception have led to many robots becoming still simpler, with some custom-made out of electric drills. Nonetheless, the role that robot camel jockeys are playing strikes at the essence of one of the main functions of AI –  replacing human labour. Hence, it seems a good case study of what might happen when human labour is replaced with machine labour, with the proviso that all case studies are by their nature, partial accounts of the array of ethical issues facing us in the many-faceted world of AI. The discussion here, likewise, can only touch on some of the multiple issues raised.

I chose this example also because this use of robots has been, at least within much of the tech literature, hailed as an example of the beneficial application of robotics (1, 2). But of course, on closer inspection, things are more complex. The challenges of this particular case study are many. These include the difficulty of being able to monitor precisely what the impact of the use of the robot camel jockeys has been, as well as complexities introduced by political, cultural and religious differences between the countries where the firms that are developing these robots are located, and the countries where robots are being commissioned and used. There are issues in international law here as well as individual and professional ethics to consider. So, although it might be an example of a very simple form of robotics, it’s an example of a highly complex ethical issue.

As such, there is much to be teased out and considered. Here are some thoughts and some findings based on the research and commentary I’ve been able to find so far. I’ve included pretty much most the material I have been able to gather online about this topic.

Discussion

The development and use of robot camel jockeys has been framed in terms of an ongoing historical narrative wherein the use of technology is hailed as the rescuer of the worst-off in the labour force, freeing them from arduous and possibly dehumanising work, as illustrated here:  ‘the standard modernist gambit of taking a crappy job and making it more bearable through mechanization will be transformed into a 21st century policy of taking appalling and involuntary servitude and eliminating it through high tech.’ (3) The use of the word ‘servitude’ here is interesting, for it includes both slavery, and working conditions close to slavery. The replacement of child camel jockeys with robots has been hailed as an ethical situation where ‘everyone will win a little’ since ‘every robot camel jockey hopping along on its improbable mount means one Sudanese boy freed from slavery and sent home’ (3); the robots are even described in one headline as ‘the robots that fight for human rights’ (2). This is held up as an example of how ‘there are some issues that can really be solved with innovation and technology’ (Lara Hussein, UNICEF) (4).

Camel racing is an old tradition in the Gulf States, including Saudi Arabia, Qatar, Kuwait, and the UAE (5). The use of children was common owing to their small size and lightness meaning camels could run faster. However, it is well established that children were trafficked – sold or kidnapped – from countries such as Sudan, Eritrea, Mauritania, India, Pakistan and Bangladesh, sometimes from as young as six months old (6). These children were then subjected to further extreme maltreatment, being allegedly deprived of food and sleep to remain small (3, 7), and according to reports, frequently the subject of sexual abuse (8, 9). The racing itself was onerous, frightening and often dangerous (6). There are reports of children injured or killed while racing, killed by fellow jockeys, and by trainers (6, 8).

Probably largely owing to international pressure, and as prohibited by the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child (7), the use of child camel jockeys was banned across the Gulf at varying dates starting with the UAE in 2005 (3, 5, 10). However, laws prohibiting child labour which had been in place for several years in various countries were reportedly routinely flouted (8). Anti-Slavery International commented in 2006, ‘The UAE government is proposing using robots to replace child camel jockeys. This seems a complicated alternative to implementing fair labour conditions for adult jockeys. Furthermore, the use of robot jockeys in races will not preclude the need for people to exercise, feed and care for the camels in camps.’ (7).

Rather than replacing child jockeys with adult jockeys working in reasonable conditions, replacement of children with robots occurred. Companies in Switzerland (3, 5) and Japan produced robots. The camels would not run without riders. Therefore the robots had to be made to look sufficiently human to encourage the camels to run; steps were taken to ensure that they were not so human that they violated Islamic codes about representational art (3). The successful adoption of the robots has been attributed to the fact that they were seen as ‘cool’ and high tech: ‘The motto of the day is clear: “Pimp my camel.” They laugh at the Swiss engineers for voicing technical reservations or concerns about the camels’ welfare,’ although some locals expressed dismay that robot jockeys lowered the value and status of the racing camels (11). Since first adoption, there has been a trade in custom robots made from deWalt drills which are much cheaper and more reliable (2), and at 10 kg even lighter than the children (12). Development of robot jockeys has also been encouraged as a ‘symbol of the future’ (11). A robot jockey development project was a prize-winner in the 2014-15 Khalifa Fund Technopreneur Competition.

The camel racing may take place in considerable secrecy especially since in some areas it may involve illegal gambling (2). There seems often to be few spectators, being watched on TV in certain countries, although not televised in others (3). Some reports claim that the law is openly flouted with even TV races showing child jockeys. Reporters have been banned from filming when children were involved and media in the countries involved is generally tightly controlled (6). Reports claim that robots now deliver electric shocks to the camels to increase competition (13, 14), and that malfunctioning robots cause the camels injury (15) although some claim the reverse that camels suffer fewer injuries (16). This all points to difficulties in assessing the impact of the use of robot jockeys.

Reports about the impact of robot jockeys vary wildly. Vogue even has a stylish and glamourised photo shoot of camel racing with robot jockeys in Dubai (17), whereas reports from trafficking organisations and from inside Pakistan paint a very different picture. Research has found that the number of children being admitted to hospital with injuries consistent with falling from camels has decreased since the introduction of robot jockeys (18). However, it may be that there are injured children being kept away from hospital because of the new illegality (8). Children freed from racing are reported to have serious and lasting injuries years later and to have large educational social and emotional problems; some had never seen a woman (19). Since child camel jockeys were outlawed, human rights organisation Ansar Burney Trust have however recently found that 3000 child camel jockeys are simply missing (20). It had previously been found that children under the age of 10 were apparently failing to be repatriated (7). Despite optimism about the benefits of robot jockeys, it appears that the trafficking of child jockeys may continue (2, 7, 9, 19). Human rights organisations have attempted to repatriate the children involved but few know who their families are and it has rarely been possible to reunite them with their families, some of whom sold them in the first place; homes have been set up for them e.g. in Pakistan (8). However, other reports claim that the vast majority have been returned to their families (concerning children in the UAE – UNICEF in Dubai) (21); perhaps the disparity may be explained by regional differences, by different reporting methods or by differences in observations made from ‘host’ and home countries. Families who had sold their children have been threatened with action if they attempt to resell them, and there are accounts of resentment at their return (22). It has been reported that Qatar simply shipped boys back to Sudan, where they face possible death, and that other boys stayed where they were working in other occupations or unemployed (3). Those working to assist the children have reportedly received threats (8). It has been opined that since Pakistan and Bangladesh are so dependent for income from their citizens who work in the Gulf States, little if any pressure is put on the host countries by the source countries regarding the use of child labour (pers. com), although reportedly India smashed several child selling gangs in the early 1990s (6). AntiSlavery International reports that receiving countries do little to control the entry of children (6).

Commentary

It’s clear that the notion that replacing onerous labour with robots produces a morally good outcome simplifies the issues. These are just a couple of preliminary remarks on a highly complex case.

Consider another situation: replacing human mine clearers with robots. Clearing mines is unfortunately necessary, but very dangerous work. Where possible, replacing a human being who might get killed, with a robot which might merely get blown up, is a moral no-brainer. Robots are expendable. The  kind of robotics that would be involved in this is so far from any possibility of consciousness that we can leave aside the question of whether we might attribute moral agency to mine-clearing robots. Moreover, unlike in the camel jockeys’ case, although there can be of course be moral issues regarding recruitment into the armed services, in considering the impact on human bomb disposal experts of the use of robotics, we are almost certainly not considering a scenario with trafficked minors whose fate following the implementation of robots is uncertain and possibly perilous.

But racing camels, no matter that it’s an embedded part of some cultures, can hardly be construed on the same plane of necessity. The question raised by some commentators, ‘why not just use adult jockeys?’ highlights an apparent reluctance by some camel racers to comply with international legislation. Moreover, we are not talking about onerous compliance with baffling or seemingly pointless bureaucracy. We are talking about compliance with laws against child labour, in the context of highly dangerous work, for the sake of a sport. The implication of much of the discussion is that the main impetus for compliance with anti-slavery  legislation was the use of robot camel jockeys, rather than a change of heart about the impacts on the child jockeys.

I commented above how the description of the child camel jockeys’ work as ‘servitude’ elides the difference between slavery and working conditions that are close to slavery. In some reports, the notion of slavery is used openly, in others, this issue is skated around or bypassed. Orienting the ethical discussion to the narrative of slavery, rather than to the narrative of technology as a force that throughout history can make incremental improvements in people’s  lives, may make a difference to how the question is tackled. Here is a thumbnail sketch of a momentous ethical debate: If something as morally offensive as child slavery is occurring, is it best to do whatever one can to improve the situation? Or is it best to keep one’s hands clean and refuse to have anything to do with those who are responsible? Both cases can be argued to have some merit.

Claims of moral and cultural relativism might conceivably rear their heads in this instance, to bypass the issue of responsibility for involvement with camel racing, (notwithstanding the existence of ratified international legislation accepted by the governments of the states in question); but really? In considering the situation, although conditions may well have varied in different countries and with different owners, one would have to err on the safe side regarding reports of the treatment of the child jockeys. Selling children, food deprivation, emotional deprivation, sleep deprivation, total lack of education, participation in a dangerous sport – all okay because of moral relativism? Not worrying about the fate of these children, that’s just what goes on elsewhere – really? You need to find yourself another philosopher if you want a debate that entertains that argument seriously.

What of individual or corporate moral responsibility in regard to manufacturing and supplying robot camel jockeys? A response to the intransigence of camel racers who were not complying with anti-slavery legislation could be force, or alternatively, attempts to produce a shift in moral consciousness. The latter is likely to be harder, and the neither are realistically easily in the power of a few individuals or small companies. Robotics manufacturers are small beer in this context. It’s not at all obvious that robotics manufacturers who step in to the fray have any responsibility to try to produce a change in the moral outlook of the camel racers themselves, since how could they? On the other hand, one might wonder if by working with camel racers, one becomes to an extent complicit with the morally problematic treatment of the child camel jockeys. One might wonder even if by their involvement, robotics manufacturers had any responsibility to monitor the fate of the child camel jockeys. On the other hand, it’s plausible to consider moral responsibility as distributed among different parties depending upon their location and their powers, and consider that it’s the job of other organisations and parties to track the fate of the former child jockeys and to assess if child servitude persists in other forms. This is a very large and very difficult task.

But at the least, in this complex situation, it would be best to exercise caution in claiming unproblematic success for the implementation of robot camel jockeys. It should be apparent how hard it would be for any professional code of ethics to make clear statements about engaging in such work. The example also shows how presenting the issue in different ways, and looking at it from different angles, can produce varied ethical reactions.

It also illustrates a central lesson for uses of AI which replace human labour – take a very close look at what happens to the human beings who are thereby displaced.

And consider the more general question of how we go about considering ethics and technology. This case study illustrates something interesting – how the technology, even something as simple as this, can get glamourised – the Vogue photo shoot, and the phrase ‘pimp my camel’, stand out here. Assessing the glamour of robotics here is complex, and messy. This is a recurring theme in technology in general (the shiny, sexy sort of tech at least, and robotics and AI in many forms qualifies here). The seductive lure of technology can perhaps lead us to overestimate what moral impact it has on a situation, possibly misconstruing the complexities and being blinded to other elements, which we see in the rush of some to praise robotics for dashing to the rescue of the child jockeys. On the other hand, the seductive lure of technology might just have done the trick of persuading some camel racers to replace children with machines.

This morality tale echoes Pinocchio in reverse (23). Pinocchio was a puppet whose father longed for him to become a real boy; Pinocchio himself of course wished for this too. But in some regions of the world of camel racing, real boys have been reduced to puppets. In the case of the use of robot camel jockeys, the equation of a child with a mere expendable thing pragmatically works to advantage, where a mere thing – the robot – is considered to be better than a child. In Pinocchio’s story, it was the development of moral character that did the trick, and Pinocchio became a real boy when he sacrificed his safety to rescue his father; in the Disney version, he has to prove himself to be brave, truthful and unselfish. Whilst on occasion and pragmatically, a quick technological fix might be the least worst option, if we exchange such elements of moral growth for a technological fix too often, in the long run the world might not be much better off.

The way in which AI typically acts to replace or supplement human labour is going to present immensely complex challenges for ethics. Embedding these considerations within professional codes of ethics will be far from straightforward.

Paula Boddington

We would like to thank the Future of Life Institute for sponsoring our work

  1. Moor JH. The nature, importance, and difficulty of machine ethics. Intelligent Systems, IEEE. 2006;21(4):18-21.
  2. Brook P. The DIY robots that ride camels and fight for human rights. Wired. 2015(03.03.15).
  3. Lewis J. Robots of Arabia. Wired. 2005(11.1.05).
  4. Rasnai A. Dubai’s Camel Races Embrace Robot Jockeys. The Daily Beast. 2013.
  5. Pejman P. Mideast: rehabilitation for retired child camel jockeys gets top priority IPS News2005 [Available from: http://www.ipsnews.net/2005/05/mideast-rehabilitation-for-retired-child-camel-jockeys-gets-top-priority/.
  6. Gluckman R. Death in Dubai 1992: http://www.gluckman.com/camelracing.html.
  7. International A-s. Information on the United Arab Emirates (UAE) Compliance with ILO Convention No.182 on the Worst Forms of Child Labour (ratified in 2001) Trafficking of children for camel jockeys. 2006.
  8. Williamson L. Child camel jockeys find hope BBC News; 2005/02/04 [Available from: http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/1/hi/world/south_asia/4236123.stm.
  9. Lillie M. Camel Jockeys in the UAE: Human Trafficking Search; 2013 [Available from: http://humantraffickingsearch.net/wp/camel-jockeys-in-the-uae/.
  10. Knight W. Robot camel jockeys take to the track. New Scientist. 2005(21 July).
  11. Schmundt H. Camel Races: Robotic Jockeys Revolutionize Desert Races. Speigel Online International. 18/07/2005 ed2005.
  12. Watson I. Robot Jockeys Give Camel Racing a Modern Twist: NPR; 2007 [Available from: http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=10304576.
  13. Spooky. The camel-riding robot jockeys of Arabia. 2011. http://www.odditycentral.com/pics/the-camel-riding-robot-jockeys-of-arabia.html
  14. Wafa I. “Shock jockey” sellers arrested. The National UAE. 2011 20/01/2011.
  15. Nasir Z. Of camel jockeys and camels. The Nation. 2013 08/07/2013.
  16. Nowais SA. UAE camel trainers prefer robot jockeys. The National UAE. 2015 13/06/2015.
  17. Shaheen S. Meet the Camel-Riding Robot Jockeys in Dubai. Vogue.
  18. Abu-Zidan FM, Hefny AF, Branicki F. Prevention of Child Camel Jockey Injuries: A Success Story From the United Arab Emirates. Clinical Journal of Sport Medicine. 2012;22(6):467-71.
  19. Gishkori. Camel jockeys: Popular Arab sport costs Pakistani children their sanity. The Express Tribune Pakistan. 2013 8/05/2013.
  20. AnsarBurneyTrust. Almost three thousand under age camel jockeys missing: ansarburney.org; 2013 [Available from: http://ansarburney.org/almost-three-thousand-underage-child-camel-jockeys-missing/.
  21. United Arab Emirates: Camel racing continues to be child free: IRIN Humanitarian news; 2006 [updated 24/12/2006. Available from: http://www.irinnews.org/report/62903/united-arab-emirates-camel-racing-continues-to-be-child-free.
  22. Pakistan; Former child camel jockeys and the struggle to return home: IRIN Humanitarian news; 2007 [updated 3/01/2007. Available from: http://www.irinnews.org/report/62967/pakistan-former-child-camel-jockeys-and-the-challenge-to-return-home.
  23. Jordan B. Peterson provides an interesting and illuminating discussion of the moral significance of the Pinocchio story on which I drew in considering these questions and which can be found in a lecture for his course Maps of Meaning which can be seen at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=AdAdf4watJQ

We would like to thank the Future of Life Institute for sponsoring this work.

The Distinctiveness of AI Ethics, and Implications for Ethical Codes

The Distinctiveness of AI Ethics, and Implications for Ethical Codes

Paula Boddington

Paper presented at the workshop Ethics for Artificial Intelligence, July 9th 2016, IJCAI-16, New Yorkfuture

Abstract

If workable codes or guidance on ethics and AI are to be produced, the distinctive ethical challenges of AI need to be faced head on. The purpose of this paper is to identify several major areas where AI raises distinctive or acute ethical challenges, with a view to beginning an analysis of challenges and opportunities for progress in these areas. Seven areas described are: Hype in AI, and its unfortunate consequences; The interface between technology and wider social or human factors; Uncertainty about future technological development and its impact on society; Underlying philosophical questions; Professional vulnerability in the face of emerging technology; An additional layer of complexity in ethical codes, concerning machine behaviour; The extension, enhancement, or replacement of core elements of human agency.

1              Introduction

This paper arises from work undertaken as part of an FLI project entitled ‘Towards a code of ethics for AI’. The purpose of this project is not to produce a code of ethics as such, but to clarify and analyse the challenges and purposes of producing such codes.

This presentation concerns some potential challenges to producing workable, transparent codes, guidance, or regulation in the field of AI. In this endeavour, we should not presuppose that AI raises any more serious ethical problems than other areas of technology, nor that its problems are completely unique. In many respects, indeed, AI raises issues which have broad similarities with other areas; but the focus here will be on particular respects in which AI does raise issues that are distinctive or unique. Insofar as these bear similarities to other areas, there can be mutual learning; but insofar as they are AI-specific, particularly hard attention must be given to unravelling them.

Our work has looked at several areas where these issues arise, which will be considered in turn in what follows:

  1. Hype in AI, and its unfortunate consequences;
  2. The interface between technology and wider social or human factors;
  3. Uncertainty about future technological development and its impact on society;
  4. Underlying philosophical questions;
  5. Professional vulnerability in the face of emerging technology;
  6. An additional layer of complexity in ethical codes, concerning machine behaviour;
  7. The extension, enhancement, or replacement of core elements of human agency.

2              Hype in AI, and its unfortunate consequences

There is a lot of hype concerning many technologies, and in particular their ethical implications, as we have seen with genomics and nanotechnologies [Caulfield, 2012], for example. In the case of AI, this hype is now virtually at fever pitch [Hawking, 2015], with some prominent individuals recently claiming that AI presents ‘an existential threat’ to humanity. Whether or not such concerns are overblown, this very hype itself will have impacts.

2.1          Angels and bad guys

One impact, which can be quite considerable, is that fear of being branded one of the ‘bad guys’ may lead to individual or collective attempts to promote oneself as on the side of the angels. Such positioning might be for intrinsic or strategic reasons (e.g. the EPSRC meeting on the Principles of Robotics explicitly aimed to avoid the sort of public aversion which the UK public had shown to GM [Bryson, 2012]. But at its worst, appearing to be ethical might trump actually being ethical.

2.2          Virtue signalling and exclusion of the under-resourced

Secondly, this positioning might have an effect upon the very content of the codes, for example by including largely vacuous material that is little more than ‘virtue signalling’ [Bartholemew, 2015], with empty displays of ethical probity (‘we are passionate about the future of the human race’ , ‘we believe that AI should be used for the benefit of the whole of humankind’, etc). More tangibly, attempts have been made to urge ethical behaviours on a group which would exclude both those who disagree, and less well-resourced members: it’s easier to be ethical the richer you are. This can be seriously prejudicial against the least privileged, unless special provision is given or attention paid to the issue [Boddington, 2011, ch 10].

Thus otherwise laudable policy can end up inadvertently excluding the actors who are least well resourced, especially if it focuses too much on the most ‘visible’ ethical questions, without considering them in context. Data-sharing policies in genomics provide one clear example here, biasing procedures against those who are unable – perhaps for resource reasons – to reciprocate.

For an example from AI, the IIIM’s Ethics Policy for Peaceful R&D eschews military funding, and will only collaborate with civilian researchers if they have received no more than 15% of their funding from military sources in the last 5 years [IIIM]. The preamble to this policy makes explicit political statements, including that military funding is commonly defended by reference to an increased ‘“terrorist threat”’ (with scare quotes that clearly imply scepticism); it also endorses the ‘brave’ actions of Edward Snowden. Researchers who are not in the position of finding alternative sources of funds may therefore be excluded from potentially beneficial collaboration. (So far, this is not to comment on the rights or wrongs of the IIIM’s stance, merely to use it as an example of how policy may lead to differential impact for different actors within the world of AI research.)

2.3          Methodological impacts – alleged novelty and comprehensiveness

Thirdly, hyping up the uniqueness of the issues in AI will also have important effects on the methodology of how ethical questions are addressed. For if an ethical question is seen to be (in part, at least) an old question applied in a new context, then one can argue with reference to previous applications, but if a question is presented as being new and unique, then it will be approached very differently. Such framing can be vital, because example choice and description – including both language and institutional context – significantly affects how ethical questions are understood and developed [Chambers, 1999; Fischer et al 1993; Rein et al 1993; Taburrini 2015].

Take, for example, the framing remark: ‘everything that civilisation has to offer is a product of human intelligence’ [Hawking, 2015]. This misleadingly suggests that everything in society derives from design and intelligence, and may lead to hubristic discounting of serendipity, circumstance and pure accident. It can also divert attention from how ethical issues raised by any technology are a complex result of many factors (see below), misleadingly focusing on aspects of a situation that are designed into it, as the expense of those that are contingent or emergent.

2.4          Viewing the landscape through the lens of the hyped technology

Another risk of hype is that the consequent emphasis on the new technology will distort perceptions of the moral context, interpreting it in terms of that (perhaps problematic) technology at the expense of others. As an example from biotechnology, the UK’s HFEA recently sanctioned mitochondrial transfer techniques (so-called ‘3 person IVF’) to combat transmission of mitochondrial disease from mother to child. The HFEA praised the technique ‘giving the chance of having a healthy child’ [HFEA 2013]. But these women could already have children through surrogacy, or gestate a child with a donated egg. So the description of the technique’s advantages tacitly presupposed a particular notion of what it is to have ‘your own child’ (viz. with maternal nuclear DNA), thus eclipsing other, older reproductive techniques that the same organisation also supports and regulates [HFEA]. Though less morally serious, a similar pattern can be seen in the progressive development of information technology, for example in respect of demands made for administrative and ‘audit’ information, whereby as new possibilities have become practicable (e.g. the generation of huge amounts of printed information), these possibilities have often come to be seen as absolutely necessary, usually without careful consideration of the costs and benefits. Thus the new technology shapes our vision, without any careful prior judgement that it is appropriate.

3              The interface between technology and wider social or human factors

Related to the issue of hype is the risk that excitement over the potential of AI and its technological possibilities will lead us to overlook complex social and institutional factors, which may affect how the relevant questions are framed, understood and addressed. These factors are also crucial for the enforcement or influence of any code of ethics, many of which remain unread or ignored [MacLean, Elkind 2004]. The institutional or political driver to the production of such codes is likely to be more concrete than the abstract encouragement of ethical behaviour: for example a wish to avoid public backlashes or lawsuits, to encourage funding, to signal the virtue of the UK in ethical regulation (again perhaps to attract funding), and generally to be seen as virtuous (which is not of course quite the same as the desire to be virtuous). To take a balanced view of these things – and to avoid confusing ethics with public relations – the specific institutional, political, financial and economic context of the creation and use of AI must be properly considered.

4              Uncertainty about the future of the technology and its implications for society

The future of any rapidly developing technology is hard to predict, and not only for technological reasons (since economic, political, social, and other factors can often intervene). Appropriate ethical judgments to new developments are also impossible to anticipate, since attitudes may evolve with the technology, as we have seen in recent debates about privacy, where views vary greatly depending on the context, in ways that could not have been foreseen [Nissenbaum, 2010, 2004]. In the case of AI, these points are especially pertinent, given how far AI could potentially impact upon how we think and relate to each other, and on vital elements of society such as modes of production.

One popular response to this evident impossibility of producing future-proofed codes of ethics in areas of rapid development or contextual uncertainty is to stress the importance of equipping researchers and professionals with the ethical skills to make nuanced decisions in context – to refer to virtue ethics [AOIR 2012, Atkinson 2009]. But virtue ethics is especially badly placed to provide any such panacea when dealing with technology which is likely to bring broad ranging and unpredictable change in central areas of human life. For the dominant model of virtue ethics – inherited from Aristotle – is predicated on a stable and slow-changing society, where the young can learn virtues from the older and wiser who possess phronesis, or practical wisdom. This model is hopeless when the need is to develop a new model of practical wisdom, to cope with future realities many of which probably cannot yet even be conceived, let alone anticipated.

5              Background philosophical questions

Fundamental questions, such as what it means to be human, or what ultimate values we should be pursuing, can readily arise in areas of rapidly developing technology. In genomics and genetics, for example, questions about the ‘essence’ of humanity can appear in debates about what is ‘natural’ or ‘unnatural’, what genetic interventions count as curing disease (as opposed to creating a ‘designer baby’), how the future of humanity might be altered via germline alterations; whether we in fact face a ‘post-human’ future, or whether the human race might diverge into two or more species. A proper approach would involve teasing out the different understandings and assumptions involved, how exactly these relate to the practical ethical questions, and considering how far the deep philosophical issues can be resolved sufficiently, or bypassed, to allow those practical questions to be addressed. But too often the fundamental issues – so far from provoking corresponding deep and careful thinking – can be overdramatised, leading to idealised or rarefied notions of what is ‘natural’ or ‘really’ human, and thus obscuring the issues rather than clarifying them.

Some of these questions arise also in AI. Will interaction between humans and intelligent machines change our natures in some significant ways, and might the future bring hardware interactions between humans and machines – another possible aspect, perhaps, of a post-human future? Will we find ourselves no longer the ‘crown of creation’ but subordinate to superintelligent machines? A distinctive hallmark of how these questions arise in AI is that they focus on mental aspects of what it is to be human – concerning agency, decision and choice – including for instance questions about responsibility and accountability, as well as what counts as human intelligence. Often such debates focus on extrapolated and imagined future agency within AI, commonly contrasted simplistically with idealised and uncontextualised notions of human agency.

As one example, in the context of Lethal Autonomous Weapons, it is sometimes argued that these violate the human right to be killed with dignity by a soldier who is acting in full moral consciousness of the fact that they are taking a human life [Champagne, Tonkins 2015; Sparrow 2007]. But, putting aside the highly debatable question of whether there is any dignity at all in being killed in war, this argument implausibly idealises the actions of the average soldier. Of course, each human being will always retain their own moral responsibility; but qua solider, an agent will be following a chain of military command while on the battlefield. Excepting special circumstances where a soldier has reason to consider that something has gone seriously awry with the chain of command and that the rules of war are being broken, obedience is required and reasonably expected – so the soldier’s time for full and conscious moral reflection was during enlisting: by the time of battle, that opportunity has gone. Moreover, it’s morally cruel to expect our best young soldiers – when having to kill in the heat of dangerous battle for our benefit – to pause to reflect in full consciousness ‘this is a human being that I alone am responsible for killing’. In normal circumstances, such responsibility lies more with military command and the politicians who called for war in the first place. Military robots then may be being held up to faulty idealisation.

6              Professional vulnerability in the face of emerging technology is magnified with AI

One motivating reason for the existence of professional codes of conduct is the relative vulnerabilities of professional versus others: clients, and the general public. It’s assumed that professionals have capacities and knowledge which others lack, or possess to a much lesser degree, and that therefore, professionals must use their skills and knowledge wisely and to the general good. But one of the major issues flagged in relation to AI is the fear that even the professionals might be relatively vulnerable themselves – that AI will become too complex to understand, and possibly to control – especially given the very fast pace at which it is able to operate [Bostrom 2014]. Hence, any ethical codes for AI need to take account of debates about the possible limited capacity of AI researchers to understand, anticipate and control their very products. This does not make AI unique per se – there have also, for example, been worries about biotechnology ‘escaping the lab’ [Koepsell 2009] – but the extent of these fears with respect to AI are probably greater than with any other technology. This issue of control is intimately linked to the following issue, and the two together imply that producing codes of ethics for AI will be particularly challenging, whatever one thinks of the question of how much autonomy AI has or will develop.

7              An additional layer of complexity is required in ethical codes for AI, concerning machine behaviour

Codes of ethics for the professions deal with the behaviour of professionals, and the consequences of the products or services they produce. But in AI, a special feature is that there is a layer of machine behaviour which also needs regulatory attention (and this is true regardless of debates about the genuineness of machine ‘intelligence’). The fact that AI can act in ways unforeseen by its designer raises issues about the ‘autonomy’, ‘responsibility’ and decision-making capacities of AI, and hence of the relation to human autonomy, responsibility, decision and control. If we try to address these issues at a very general level, we risk falling into vagueness and vacuity. So as a general principle, it is likely to be far more productive to attempt to work through these sorts of problems within particular concrete settings of application. When this is done, complex and potentially obscure philosophical debates may even be avoided entirely (as we shall see below).

8              The extension, enhancement, or replacement of core elements of human agency

This is a hallmark of AI, and although all machines enhance human powers to some extent, AI has the potential to do so more effectively than any other technology to date. Three main points deserve stressing here:

8.1          Economic and social effects

First, the potential of AI raises questions beyond the remit of AI researchers per se, such as when considering the wider societal impacts of large shifts in wealth creation and modes of production. Such issues as whether wealth should be systematically redistributed to compensate for the job losses occasioned by AI [Brynjolfsson, McAfee, 2014; Frey, 2013] cannot plausibly be dealt with by any realistic or achievable professional code of ethics. But these issues do serve to illustrate how simplistic it is to presume that calls for ‘beneficial AI’ can be interpreted and applied straightforwardly, even if they are agreed. Whether some application of AI counts as overall ‘beneficial’ might well depend on the economic and social structure within which it is embedded, far beyond the control of AI researchers.

8.2          AI within human systems

Secondly, in many cases, AI will enter complex systems of human agency, making it necessary that codes of ethics deal adequately with this interface. Consider, for example, the use of robotics within a hospital ward. Such places are highly complex systems with lines of responsibility and accountability which are partly formalised and partly informal, and which often change in response to circumstance and policy. Often, also, the lines of responsibility, reporting, and duty may be fragmented, duplicated and overlapping. Robots placed within such as system – whether or not they themselves are considered as responsible agents – will certainly displace some human nodes of responsibility and accountability [Daykin, Clarke, 2000]. Thus careful analysis of the effects of robotic placement within such systems is vital, and codes of ethics need to recognise this complexity. In this light, the EPSRC’s Principles of Robotics – which simply describes robots as ‘products’, and explicitly ascribes responsible agency only to humans, never robots [Boden et al 2011] – falls badly short. A more nuanced approach is required, recognising that within a hospital system, responsibilities are understood as only partly falling on the individual, for they are also part of an entire system, and computers can perfectly well be part of such a system. Thinking in this way might also help to bypass intractable questions of the nature of ‘genuine’ responsibility, and whether robots will ever achieve it. Such questions do not need to be solved if our aim – as in the NHS – is primarily meant to be upon understanding how errors occur with a view to correcting them.

8.3          Spontaneity versus forethought

Humans and AI systems make decisions – including decisions with a moral aspect – in different ways. Close attention to this might be useful in disentangling some moral worries about AI, and clarifying relevant differences with respect to codes of ethics. For example, humans may be forgiven for some decisions, in circumstances where higher standards would be expected of an AI (something like an idealised human standard, perhaps). Consider the concern that has been expressed regarding how an autonomous vehicle might react in a crash situation where a choice has to be made about who might be killed or injured, depending upon what actions are taken [Russell et al 2015]. But discussion of these things – though commonly voiced as an objection to autonomous vehicles – commonly takes for granted that a higher standard of decision-making can reasonably be expected of them. Thus, for example, a human being can often be forgiven for a suboptimal decision made under duress and in haste, and could also be forgiven for e.g. trying to save themselves or their families in a dangerous situation. But we are much less likely to ‘forgive’ a decision conceived and programmed beforehand. This prejudice may or may not have any rational basis in deeper ethical foundations. But it impacts on the consideration of autonomous vehicles, which have to be designed ‘in the cold light of day’ to react appropriately in emergency situations. From one point of view, such careful advance consideration seems ethically superior to the ‘it’ll be alright on the night’ approach; but from another point of view, it’s less, well, ‘human’. Such double-edged complexity abounds when considering replacing human labour and agency with AI. Again, this short discussion is far from complete, but serves only to flag the importance of considering elements of timing, planning, and the agentic source of decision making, in considering the ethics of AI.

9              Conclusions

There are numerous challenges in considering the ethical issues that AI faces us with, and further challenges in developing codes of ethics, guidance or other regulations for ethically robust AI. Although we are faced with much distracting hype which perhaps distorts some of the issues and their import, nonetheless, careful examination of the particular and distinct issues which AI presents us with can help us in understanding these further. Addressing these challenges will require input from both the AI community and more widely.

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Peter Millican for his careful commentary on the manuscript, as well as to Michael Wooldridge for discussion.

This work has been kindly supported with a grant from the Future of Life Institute

References

[AoIR Ethical Decision-Making and Internet Research: Recommendations from the AoIR Ethics Working Committee (Version 2.0). 2012.

[Atkinson P. Ethics and ethnography. Twenty-First Century Society. 2009;4(1):17-30.

[Bartholmew J. Hating the Daily Mail is a substitute for doing good. The Spectator. 2015(April 18th 2015).

[Boddington P. Ethical Challenges in Genomics Research: a guide to understanding ethics in context. Heidelberg: Springer; 2011.

[Boden M, Bryson J, Caldwell D, Dautenhahn K, Edwards L, Kember S, et al. Principles of Robotics. Swindon, UK: Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council ESPRC, 2011.

[Bostrom N. Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014.

[Brynjolfsson E, McAfee A. The Second Machine Age: Work, Progress, and Prosperity in a Time of Brilliant Technologies. New York: W.N. Norton &n Company; 2014.

[Bryson J. The making of the EPSRC Principles of Robotics. AISB quarterly. 2012;133(Spring 2012):14-5.

[Caulfield T, Condit C. Science and the Sources of Hype. Public Health Genomics. 2012;15(3-4):209-17.

[Chambers T. The Fiction of Bioethics (Reflective Bioethics). New York: Routledge; 1999.

[Champagne M, Tonkens R. Bridging the Responsibility Gap in Automated Warfare. Philos Technol. 2015;28(1):125-37.

[Daykin N, Clarke B. ‘They’ll still get the bodily care’. Discourses of care and relationships between nurses and health care assistants in the NHS. Sociology of Health & Illness. 2000;22(3):349-63.

[Fischer F, Forrester J. Editor’s Introduction. In: Fischer F, Forrester J, editors. The Argumentative Turn in Policy and Planning. Durham and London: Duke University Press; 1993. p. 1-17.

[Frey C, Osborne M. The Future of Employment: How Susceptible Are Jobs to Computerisation? Oxford: Oxford Martin School, University of Oxford, 2013.

[Hawking S, Russell S, Tegmark M, Wilczek F. Stephen Hawking: ‘Transcendence looks at the implications of artificial intelligence – but are we taking AI seriously enough?’. The Independent. 2014 May 1st 2014.

[HFEA. HFEA agrees advice to Government on the ethics and science of mitochondria replacement [press release]. London2013.

[Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. Available from: http://www.hfea.gov.uk/.

[IIM. Ethics Policy for Peaceful R&D. Reykjavik, Iceland: Icelandic Institute for Intelligent Machines.

[Koepsell D. On Genies and Bottles: Scientists’ Moral Responsibility and Dangerous Technology R&D. Sci Eng Ethics. 2009;16(1):119-33.

[McLean B, Elkind P. The Smartest Guys in the Room: The Amazing Rise and Scandalous Fall of Enron: Portfolio; 2013, 2004.

[Nissenbaum H. Privacy as Contextual Integrity. Washington Law Review. 2004;79(1):119-58.

[Nissenbaum H. Privacy in Context: Technology, Policy and the Integrity of Social Life. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press; 2010.

[Rein M, Schon D. Reframing Policy Discourse. In: Fischer F, Forrester J, editors. The Argumentative Turn in Policy and Planning. Durham and London: Duke University Press; 1993. p. 145-66.